In 2014, the number of Chinese Internet users reached 649 million, which represents 47.9 percent of China's population. At the same time, the number of mobile phone Internet users reached almost 557 million. However, the Chinese government has been criticizing the framework of so‐called Western values in which the use of the Internet is purportedly embedded, and accusing the United States of its “Internet imperialism” (Tan ; Min ). This accusation is not merely politically motivated, or philosophically groundless. Chinese scholars have long been arguing that cyber communication and interaction cultivate a sense of selfish individualism and moral nihilism, and that these might challenge and corrupt Confucian values (Yuan and Zeng, ; Chen and Chen, ; Zhou ). Therefore, we need to address whether Internet use is compatible with Confucian values, when it is generally agreed that Confucianism continues to have a significant influence on Chinese culture, and, at least to a certain extent, continues to underlie the mentality of the Chinese people (Bell ; Yu and Zhao ).

In this article, I shall explore the philosophical question of whether Internet use, particularly social network services (SNS), is compatible with the fundamental values and, norms of Confucian ethics; and, if it is compatible, I will address whether Confucian ethics can make a different SNS. I will first review the arguments of Bockover () and Wong (), who hold that Internet use might be fundamentally incompatible with Confucian ethics. Based on my critical responses to their studies, I will further explore how Confucianism may accommodate SNS through proper reconstruction. Specifically, I will zoom in on the notion of tian xia (under heaven), and elaborate the Confucian understanding of the moral space and its relation with the SNS. More concretely, I shall argue that it would be wrong to assume that Internet use cannot be plausibly thought to cohere with Confucianism. Instead, the notion of tian xia, as a basic structuring principle of Confucian philosophy, provides an account of moral space in which all inhabitants of the world are thought to participate as members—as different individuals—who are moral equals. I will argue that this idea could be reconstructed so as to accommodate and innovate different SNS.

Bockover and Wong: Confucianism is Incompatible with Internet Use

Bockover () and Wong () made the first systematic philosophical attempts to argue that Confucianism is incompatible with Internet use, arguing that it is not clear that the core values and norms that ground Confucian ethics are not in direct conflict with Internet use. Surprisingly, since their articles were published, no specific follow‐up work was carried out. I will now discuss their specific arguments with the aim of contributing to this novel discussion.

Mary Bockover. Bockover attacks criticisms of China's Internet policy, which stresses that it infringes on rights to freedom. She commences with the empirical observation that “the Internet is currently the most effective form of communication available to promote the first‐world value of autonomy” (Bockover , 163). For her, the spread of Internet access is driven by ideas of consumerism, free expression, equal opportunity, and free trade. This stands in sharp moral contrast with the traditional Confucian system of values (Bockover , 163). Specifically, she states: “Anyone who has Internet access can say anything and be heard, and even believed, if the presentation is convincing enough. This is allowed because it is based on the American value of free expression” (Bockover , 165).

What Bockover means to say is that the Internet is not a value‐neutral technology; rather, both in its justification and application, the Internet embraces a specific comprehensive conception of freedom. Individual freedom is methodologically treated, by Bockover, as political and personal autonomy, which means that one should have authority (rights) over specific goods above and beyond the power of the state. Bockover argues that even this freedom has been contested throughout American history in specific cases, and that the whole development of the concept of freedom in the Anglo‐American philosophical tradition has been historically complex. The adoption of the Internet can be justified by referring to specific values, for example, freedom of speech; also, its technical structure is such that its very application promotes exactly the values and concepts associated with consumerism, free trade, and so on.

The specific concept of freedom embedded in the Internet, Bockover argues, is inspired by authors such as Mill and Locke, and termed “absolutist” by Kant (Bockover , 166). Bockover argues further that we find no comparable concept of freedom in Confucian ethics. The Confucian viewpoint yields a relational concept of the person, who is thought of in terms of interdependence and duties towards others. As such, freedom is not something that can be conceptualized as if it were a right to which an atomized individual has a claim (Bockover , 164). For Bockover, it is indeed not clear whether the Confucian view of freedom is at all central to ethics; and yet, this should not be understood as a hiatus or flaw in the Confucian framework. The idea is that we cannot legitimately claim that any Western concept is “right” and the Confucian one is “wrong.” We ought to remain open to the possibility that Confucian values may be in conflict with the use of the Internet.

However, Bockover's argument is too broad. The Internet, as a tool, can be used to achieve political or simply apolitical purposes, and Confucianism, as an umbrella term, covers various schools of thought. Bockover's quotes of Confucianism are mainly from pre‐Qin (before 221bce) Confucianism, thus excluding later developments and therefore missing other possible interpretations that may not be in direct conflict with Internet adoption. However, her criticisms apply particularly well to the use of SNS, as these particular applications fit well with her description of the Internet as a tool that allows free end‐to‐end communication.

In addition, her empirical observations on the development of the Internet industry in China have become outdated. More than half of the Chinese population is now “wired up”; this is certainly beyond the vision of Bockover. However, her philosophical critique on the interplay between Confucian ethics and Internet use makes sense regardless of empirical inputs, as it maybe more of a conceptual exploration. I shall come back to evaluate these aspects of her argument in detail later on.

Wong Pak‐hang. Wong () recently responded to the compatibility concern, focusing especially on nature and the role of social media. He agrees with Bockover on the point that Internet use might be incompatible with Confucian ethics and he further extends her argument to discuss the possible interplay between the Confucian concept of the good life and the use of social media in the Web 2.0 age. With Web 2.0, people can now contribute directly to online content, making social media extremely popular. Wong, based on Boyd's (, 49) work, discusses three features of social media that are potentially in conflict with Confucian ethics: (1) the invisible audiences, (2) the collapsed contexts, and (3) the blurring of public and private. I will now briefly discuss these in turn.

First, Wong states that Confucian ethics understand moral action as role‐based: one's duties, to act in accordance with rites (li), are embedded in and determined by the specific social role or position that one adopts. To act in accordance with li means something different for a father than it does for a king; thus, moral action is predicated on the knowledge of the web of social relations and one's own specific role therein. However, since anonymity is a characteristic of online communication, such knowledge becomes impossible: the audience, one's social peers, become invisible in the sense that one cannot, with any degree of certainty, know who is engaging; this appears to be in direct conflict with the concept of moral action (Wong , 290).

Second, and relatedly, is the point about the collapse of context. Wong states, “Contexts are ethically constitutive of the Confucian way of life, as they require people to have a proper set of conducts and attitudes which are context‐dependent” (Wong , 291). The potential problem posed by SNS is that the lines that separate contexts from each other become blurred or even disappear; as such, the entire concept of cyber communication, characterized precisely by the absence of the regulating force of context, is in tension with Confucian ethics, as the later demands contextual information for having a meaningful communication. A Confucian needs to know where he is so as to act according to certain rites designed specifically for the contexts (Wong , 291).

Lastly, the blurring of the public and private spheres would be problematic from the Confucian viewpoint. According to Wong's interpretation of Confucianism, the familial sphere is very important for Confucian ethics. It is the root of morality, in the sense that familial relationships are “prototypical natural affecting relationships,” wherein one first learns how to be moral. Wong argues that Confucianism regards all nonfamilial relationships as extensions of the moral relation and concomitant obligations one holds towards one's family members (Wong , 289). Nevertheless, in line with Boyd, Wong holds that since people, regardless of their awareness about the matter, tend to post more of their private/familial information online to the public, the borderline between public and private spheres becomes increasingly less obvious. As such, he concludes that the blurring of public and private infringes upon the familial sphere, and as such it stands in direct conflict with the entire concept of moral action (Wong , 292).

Wong thus shares Bockover's conclusion that Internet use may very well be in conflict with Confucian ethics, but has provided an elaboration and specification of this claim. Wong's argument could be reconstructed as meaning that the internal structure of the Internet inherently forms an infringement upon how Confucianism understands sociomoral space. This is an interesting claim, and if it holds, indeed suggests a problem with the compatibility or even the incompatibility of Internet use and Confucianism. I will now evaluate Bockover and Wong's arguments.

Bockover and Wong Revisited

Confucianism and the right to individual freedom

To recast, Bockover holds that the notion of a right to individual freedom is arguably grounded in the Anglo‐American tradition, and stands in tension with Confucianism's conception of personhood. Indeed, in Confucianism, the person is understood as a role‐based agent who is required to act in accordance with rites; thus individual freedom, in the sense of a free choice of lifestyles, is not importantly considered in Confucianism. The concept of freedom, which affirms this understanding of individuality, is often constructed in the Western context as the right that one should have against the power of the state or the power of other individuals.

As such, it might not make sense for Confucian ethics to talk about the right to choose a particular lifestyle as the practice of freedom, because the person is primarily understood as a part that has a duty to contribute to the well‐being of the whole, rather than as an individual unit that has a claim right against his fellow persons. Bockover is correct in holding that Confucianism does not explicitly endorse such a concept of individual freedom. To evaluate Bockover's position with more scrutiny, for now assume that the notion of rights is also incompatible with Confucianism: does this mean that Confucianism denies any account of freedom?

I conjecture it does not. Not adopting the concept of a right to the individual freedom of choosing a better life, in terms of wealth, does not necessarily imply denying the objects that individual freedom is supposed to protect. Consider food security for example; in Confucianism, where the concept of duty adopts a central place, people have a general duty to protect and enhance the well‐being of others and of themselves. Also, it is the duty of the king to formulate proper economic policies such that his people live a decent life.

In the same vein, the ideas of consumerism and free trade that are connected to a right to freedom might also be protected by the Confucian duty of securing well‐being. To give an example: when Mencius noticed that Xu Xing, the leader of the school for agriculture, claimed that the world would be a better place if everyone would farm for himself, he replied negatively. He asked Chen Xiang, a follower of Xu, where Xu got his cooking pot. He got it from a vendor, answered his follower. Mencius then argued that people are born with different talents, and that it benefits the welfare of all when different people should be allowed to do what they are good at (Legge , Mencius 3A: 4). As such, people should be allowed to exchange goods so that the common welfare can be achieved at the highest levels.

Therefore, although Bockover is right in attacking individual freedom arguments, her argument in general is flawed; even though Confucianism does not embrace a right to freedom, free communication on which commercial activities rely can be protected under the principle of duty.

Confucianism, anonymity, and collapsed contexts

Wong's argument regarding anonymity concerns the role‐based tenets of Confucian ethics. What is here thought to be problematic is that in cyberspace communication one does not need to reveal his (genuine) identity; this may render it difficult or even impossible to conduct oneself in a proper manner. This issue relates to the problem of collapsed context: the identity of an interlocutor constructs the context in which communication takes place, and since role‐dependent action is determined by contextual features, proper conduct, again, becomes problematic.

First, as Wong notes, anonymity and collapse of context are challenges that cyber communication poses for ethics in general, not Confucianism in particular (Wong , 291). In addition, what Wong neglects is the fact that ultimately the most fundamental duty that Confucianism advocates is that of becoming a jun zi (morally cultivated person). Along these lines, there are several cardinal virtues to be practiced regardless of one's social role, such as kindness, thriftiness, uprightness, temperateness, and honesty (Legge , Analects 1:4; 1:10; 6:23; 12:7). It thus becomes clear that although Confucianism proposes a role‐based understanding of moral duty, Confucian ethics cannot be reflexively reduced to role‐dependent obligations.

As such, it is already important to point out that where Wong initially shows bias is in failing to see that Confucianism has the potential to accommodate and regulate anonymous communication. In online communication, a Confucian could treat others as potential family members—with genuine care and gentleman‐like virtues such as kindness, uprightness, and honesty. In particular, a Confucian could take the precaution of treating all his addressees as those of higher social status than himself. If this attitude is used in initiating a communication, one can adjust to specific rituals as the addressees’ identities are progressively revealed.

Now the question that remains to be addressed is whether anonymous communication would inevitably endanger role‐based communication, particularly the communication done in the Confucian family. First, it is not problematic for a Confucian father to hold a Skype meeting with his son. The Internet can be used for providing a space in which Confucian familial rites are carried out. Although values embedded in the Internet might suggest end‐to‐end communication, the Internet does not inevitably invalidate the default setting of communication structure in (a) particular culture(s). It is as difficult for an average Confucian to find a chance to talk to his emperor, as it is for an average citizen to chat with his president. In fact, people's use of social media reflects the culture in which they reside (Boyd ).

The problem of blurring of public and private space

Wong's argument regarding the public and private spheres is informative in some aspects, but his argument is only valid based on his particular interpretation of Confucianism. However, Confucian thoughts are not monolithic, but diverse. Different schools with different moral philosophies assign different roles to the family. Zhu Xi (1130–1200), for example, sees the family as an indispensable space in which people learn morality. However, Wang Yangming (1472–1529) regards family as the space just for practicing morality.

In general, both Wang Yangming and Zhu Xi believe in universal morality, or the heavenly pattern, and yet they radically differ in who they advocate achieving it. Zhu Xi focuses on morality as knowledge; people learn to be moral by investigating things. This mentality is arguably based on his specific cosmology; he holds that morality is embedded in the cosmological order and therefore can be learned by acquiring knowledge about the cosmos. Zhu Xi adopts and further develops a yin‐yang cosmology, which ascribes certain attributes, such as brightness, heaven, fatherhood, domination, and so on, to the idea of yang and darkness, earth, motherhood, obedience, and so on, to the idea of yin, and certain relationship between them afterward (Chen , 30–59). In this context, Zhu Xi proposes observing the order of the universe in term of yin‐yang interaction, in order to help one understand morality. In this context, familial interaction becomes important, as the family is a small universe that mirrors the cosmos (Chen , 69). For instance, because women represent yin and men represent yang, the wife should be obedient to her husband.

Yet Wang Yangming, one of the most influential neo‐Confucians, holds that morality cannot at all be learned outside of one's self‐cultivation; rather, he believes that the only feasible way to achieve morality is to restore the fang xin (the lost moral conscience), which is the attribute equally carried by all. Restoring one's moral conscience demands the effort of meditation‐like self‐reflection, in addition to carrying out one's typical roles. In Wang's view, it is natural for someone to behave in accordance with his familial roles if he successfully restores his moral conscience—not the other way around: when one's moral conscience is expressed in a parent–child relationship, it is filial piety; when expressed between siblings, it is fraternity; and so on (Chen , 23).

Regarding Wong's argument, first, the problem of blurring public and private space stands strongly only if we live mainly in cyberspace. However, it is highly unlikely that our whole lives will be digitalized. Even if this were to become the case, online communication does not immediately suggest the demise of the family or the public; instead, it suggests reshaping them. The online Confucian family might be more open to the public in terms of revealing some information, as different Confucian schools might ascribe different roles to the family—that is, seeing it not as the only source of morality, thus needing to be kept closed, but merely as a space where people can practice morality, which can be made comparably open to the public; that is, people's activities at home can work as a moral example for others.

I have evaluated the theses of Wong and Bockover above; I shall now move further to argue that Confucian ethics are not only compatible with using SNS, but could positively contribute to the reengineering of it through reconstruction and articulation of the concept of tian xia, the Confucian concept that bears significant moral meaning.

The Confucian Concept of Tian Xia (Under Heaven)

The geographical and cosmological concept of tian xia.  Tian xia is a central concept in the Confucian and most noticeably in neo‐Confucian tradition. The term literally means “under heaven,” and covers at least two interpretations: one is geographical and cosmological, and the other is moral and epistemological. These two depend on each other for specification. Tian xia was historically developed in the Zhou dynasty (1046–256 bce), when the military power of the tian zi (son of heaven: the carrier of the heavenly mandate) was very tenuous. Zhou was then composed of many tribes, which were unified by zhou li (rites of zhou); these shared rites constituted a homogeneous cultural identity.

The legitimacy of zhou's authority is self‐evident, and is understood to be located at the center of the world. A geographical model is developed in order to accommodate the interpretation of its authority: the world is conceived in the form of concentric circles, from which the authority of the tian zi ripples out. The manner of governance resembles, as Du () argues, that of the process of colonization. Depending on the geographical distance to the tian zi, different obligations are ascribed to people for paying tribute to the central authority.

In this way, a very rough perception of the space of zhou is developed. What is important here though, is that the understanding of tian xia cannot be reduced to geographical space: zhou importantly also connotes “symbolic space”—that is, it refers to the cultural unity of the people ruled by tian zi. As many scholars have observed, it would be absurd to speculate about the size of the zhou by what was written in zhou li and Shang Shu (the book of history). For instance, He () rightly points out that, if we postulate the territory of zhou according to what was described in the book of guoyu, one of the classic books of the Zhou dynasty, it would be 100 million square kilometers, which is obviously impossible. He also argues that it is extremely difficult to believe that the borders of different states in zhou could form a full circle.

Therefore, tian xia is better understood as an elaboration of a cosmological order: the ancients used tian xia as a basic structuring principle that makes comprehensible the very concept of space (Wang ). As such, tian is conceived as a hemisphere covering every inch of land over which the son of heaven claimed authority. The concept of space as tian xia should thus not be taken to refer to any specific territory; precisely because it is a basic structuring principle, it does not refer to any land in particular, but encompasses all the lands below heaven.

This cosmology is then used as the basis of Confucian ethics. Tian xia is beyond the borders of separating tribes. It is therefore an all‐inclusive concept of space. In other words, tian xia is a concept that refers to an idea of a moral community of which every human being is a member. Let me discuss this in more detail.

Moral and epistemological interpretation of tian xia

As Wong () argues, in Confucianism tian (heaven) is also a fundamental normative concept. In its high and encompassing stature, tian represents the ultimate moral authority that imparts to all moral judgments their normativity. The dao of tian, the law of heaven, is the highest moral principle that functions as a normative source on the basis of which human conduct can be justified (Wong ). Tian dao is seen as possessing two generic features: first, as the ultimate natural law, it is stable and unchangeable. As Xun Kuang (1995, 109) claims, tian dao is constant, it does not preserve itself for Yao's (a sage king in China) benevolence, or perish because of Xia's (king during the shang dynasty) brutality. Tian dao is thus a normative principle that is general in that it is not dependent on the contingency of circumstance.

Second, tian dao is represented in the human world by the concept of ren (humanity), which is specified in requirements that enable people to determine what they ought to do in their daily life. Ren is specified as li (rites, which are the application of ren and prescribe the right form of conduct in specific situations). The Confucian rites prescribe a variety of acts in daily life, including how one should act properly according to his/her social roles, and how one should cultivate him or herself. People who live in tian xia (under heaven) follow tian dao (the law of heaven). So construed, the concept of tian xia is then a notion that is both general and concrete, and represents our life‐world as it is structured around the concept of ren.

To be specific, in Confucianism a true gentleman ought to relate himself to the concept of the tian xia. Contrary to understanding someone's “being‐in‐space” as if he occupies part a geographical unit, Confucians perceive his presence in tian xia as an extension of his moral cultivation. As Wang Yangming (, 968–69) notably argues, a gentlemen sees everything under heaven in himself. Tian xia is a big family, and zhong guo (the central state) is just one family member. Anyone who refuses this exerts effort to distant people and is despicable. Why Wang Yangming held such a belief can be explained by his particular understanding of our moral nature.

Wang Yangming argues that there is indeed a heavenly pattern that is the source of morality; however, the heavenly pattern is not external but internal, because it is nothing but liang zhi (human conscience) equally shared by all. For Wang, liang zhi generally has several of the following features: (1) it is intrinsically good under all circumstances; (2) it has the cognitive capacity to judge between right and wrong; and (3) it is emotional, capable of feeling shame and honor, being sympathetic and motivating people toward particular actions.

Wang argues quite explicitly that liang zhi is beyond good and evil on the practical level (Chen , 214). For him, people judge something as good or bad based on biased views towards things. One might consider grass as bad in contrast to flowers, if he concerned only with the beauty of flowers (Chen , 73). Liang zhi is however beyond any biased views and therefore cannot be judged as good or bad on the practical level. As to the question of why liang zhi is intrinsically good, various interpretations are available and no agreement is reached. One plausible interpretation, as I shall argue, is that liang zhi helps to furnish the basic structure of action, which means valuing the objects as good and setting them as one's end. As such, liang zhi should necessarily be regarded as intrinsically good as it is the precondition for all human actions, whether these actions are for good or bad purposes.

For example, when Wang Yangming was questioned by his students why the bloom and fading of a flower are independent of its spectator, he responded that there is nothing like the flower in the world of the dead (Chen , 275). This claim is certainly absurd if we understand the flower simply as a physical object. One plausible interpretation is that Wang treats the flower as a thing (shi) rather than a mere object (wu). It is in the spectator's eyes that the object appears to be the flower with the specific color and form that bears beauty and elegance in his/her aesthetic experience. The difference between a mere object and a thing is that the thing is composed of at least three elements: the physical object, the human as the agent, and the particular value relationship between them. In such an experience, not only do we recognize and respond to the object, but we also confer value on it. To label something as a tulip might only mean a particular genus of plants in the botanic sense, but to call something a flower means something beautiful and thus good and desirable. So construed, liang zhi is possessed by all equally. Wang confirmed explicitly that liang zhi is possessed by the most average people with no differences (Chen , 107).

More importantly, liang zhi is not only cognitive but inherently emotional, involving emotions that motivate people. To this specific point, Wang generally inherits from Mencius's classic discussion of the four basic emotions of humanity, as terminals of morality: for Mencius, humans embrace four hearts—the heart of compassion, the heart of shame, the heart of courtesy and modesty, and the heart of right and wrong (Legge , Mencius 2A6). When liang zhi is practiced toward specific things, it triggers these emotions, for example, when an adult is witnessing a young boy who is about to fall into a well, his liang zhi generates a strong feeling of compassion. In this line, we understand the philosophical ground on which his tian xia view is constructed: since people all equally share the same moral conscience (the heavenly pattern), they are bai xin (people with conscience) who share something in common and live together under heaven.

As such, a Confucian is expected to carry out the role of interpreting, specifying, and cultivating dao; as a family member, one is expected to respect his parents, to educate his children, and so on; as an official, one is expected to serve the government well and ping tian xia, namely, bring harmony to all who live under tian xia (Legge , The Great Learning, 357). The whole process aims to rediscover one's liang zhi and to make it efficacious so as to actualize it in the world. So construed, the space of tian xia is the extension of the moral cultivation of the gentleman, forming the basic principle structuring moral space, and obligating people to respect all bai xin, regardless of the particular state that they inhabit, because members of the land under tian xia are moral equals due to their equally possessed conscience.

It should be noted here that what I have presented here is surely not the only plausible moral philosophy which undergirds the idea of tian xia. Since Wang Yangming is the most prominent neo‐Confucian who most intensively discussed the idea of tian xia, I mainly reconstruct his discussions here. I shall now turn to discuss what this normative concept of tian xia means for SNS.

Internet and the Concept of Tian Xia: Positively Construed

Bockover's illuminating point is that Internet technology, at the engineering level, embeds certain group of values. Various studies and technology management also have taught us that the design of technology architecture is not value‐neutral but value‐laden in the sense that it shapes our thoughts by persuading us to use it in the specific ways and develop certain habits (Fogg ; IJsselsteijn et al. ). The most recent discussion on responsible research and innovation, commonly referred as RII, suggests explicitly that certain values should even be consciously structured in technology architectures (Von Schomberg ; van den Hoven and Jacob , 30–56).

As indicated above, I hold that the Confucian concept of tian xia could ground a worldview that accommodates the use of SNS, as it provides a unique sphere in which people could communicate as bai xin. More positively, as Zhao () suggests, the concept of tian xia would help to introduce a political principle of “world‐ness” that could be used, by careful reconstruction, for transcending the principle of “internationality.” If the value of universal communication means everyone should be allowed to connect with each other, regardless of their nationality, then tian xia might provide us a with a ground for embracing SNS. This particular conceptualization of space is, after all, borderless.

It is important to note that I am not arguing that the concept of tian xia immediately provides a ready‐to‐use concept as an alternative to cosmopolitanism. It is quite implausible to think so, as the concept of tian xia was developed in a context in which no clear sense of sovereignty and internationality were formulated. What I have attempted to do is to articulate the potential of such a concept for accommodating the very spirit of SNS, namely that people should be allowed to communicate freely regardless of their geographical location.

Location reconsidered

When it comes to the design of SNS in particular, the tian xia view suggests a reconsideration of the role of locality. Traditionally, exposing one's location bears at least three important meanings: first, and geographically, it indicates scientific information about one's physical place; second, and individually, it helps to claim one's interests/pride by showing where he/she actually is; third, and socially, location is perceived, often on social media, as a categorization that sorts people geographically, and in so doing, suggests communication based on this categorization: people and news nearby are suggested to users, while distant people and events are comparably ignored.

The Tian xia worldview finds no problem with the first two ways of using one's location. However, the default setting of social networks only negatively perceives the role of locality, regarding it as dividing people and their interests, and this idea is seemingly in conflict with the tian xia worldview. In contrast, tian xia requires a more positive comprehension of locality, suggesting that the location information should be used for prompting the world‐ness rather than reinforcing the localness.

As such, when the value of world‐ness is considered in the design of social media, a more sophisticated consideration of location‐enabled services should be made. First, awareness of the world‐ness should be integrated in the settings of SNS. To give a simple example, SNS could be designed, by deploying an algorithm on locality, to notify users who only follow European tweeters that they have not followed any American or Asian tweeters, who tweet about similar topics. The positive consideration of the role of location can also be done in the background. When the app suggests the influential tweeters/news to users, a proper consideration of the representation of locality should be taken into account. Surely, to do so need not necessarily introduce paternalistic concerns, but the app could let users choose if they would like to have a broader contact or not.

Second, the new idea of locality, as world‐ness, can be embedded and prompted in the functionalities of social media. As presented, the tian xia worldview regards everyone living under heaven as bai xin, who are not citizens but people with conscience. As such, bai xin is a novel identity that is different from the individual as a wolf in the Hobbesian sense, or the Christian who adopts a comprehensive religion, or citizens who are affiliated with national sovereignty. They are self‐possessing people simply because they have a conscience which allows them to develop cardinal virtues.

Thus, tian xia explicitly poses a new task of social media, that is, to cultivate the identity of bai xin, a person with conscience. SNS should therefore not be regarded as merely tools for achieving whatever purposes, but should carry positive roles for cultivating such a new identity. Formerly, we believed that the wide distribution of social media would naturally lead to the emergence of world citizens, yet it has become clear that online communities can be fragmented (Jaeger ). More proactive effort should therefore be made in formulating new online identities. In this vein, the functionalities of social media platforms could be designed to facilitate a new sense of belonging that is not based on traditional grounds, such as religion, ethnicity, citizenship, and so on, but on human conscience, which is both rational and sentimental in its nature. This brings us to my next point, that is, to reconsider the human emotion which helps us to bond on SNS.

Emotion reconsidered

Christine Korsgaard (, 151–73) has discussed, in line with Aristotle, that emotion contributes to rational activity in various ways, including making the agent more susceptible to the influence of reason, forming good habits for rational activities, and enabling us to perceive what is good. What is important is that Korsgaard obviously sees emotion not just as passive and responsive, but normatively contributive; that is to say, emotion helps us to think and act rationally or even morally. Confucian scholar Ni Peimin () suggests a similar idea, but with many differences, in one of his much‐celebrated papers on Confucian dignity. He argues that the Confucian concept of four hearts, as concrete feelings, are not just descriptive but prescriptive in the sense that these feelings not only identify us as humans but orient us toward becoming better people. In this Confucian spirit, some feelings are normative in the sense that they are not just what we have, but they are also what we should have.

The Western liberal model of person as individual, which gives much weight to personal freedom, might have a certain influence on the way emotions are presented on SNS. One can practice his or her freedom by “liking” or “unliking” others’ posts, and in so doing build a sense of connection and belonging. “Liking” and “unliking” on SNS might engage both cognitive and emotional faculties and, particularly in the case of emotions, they might encompass feeling and attitude beyond the scope of these two labels. For example, to give a “thumbs up” might mean support rather than just “liking” in the narrow sense. However, these two attitudes, as concrete feelings, broadly express one's preferences, and facilitate freedom of choice, though they exclude many more sophisticated and humanistic emotions that connect people—for instance, being compassionate, touched, honored, and so on—which lie at the core of the emotional nature of human conscience in Confucianism. Feelings that are commonly attached to our conscience, in contrast to mere individual freedom, should also be designed into the framework of SNS, if possible.

This example helps to explain how the design of current social networks facilitates a specific kind of preference‐based human connection, while impoverishing the much more sophisticated emotions that spring from our conscience. Note that I am here not suggesting specific ready‐to‐use default options that should be used for expressing people's attitudes; rather, I am challenging the legitimacy of only having “liking” and “unliking” options being dogmatically and unreflectively deployed. Considering the normative demands of tian xia, this deployment of emotion on SNS should be carefully reconsidered.

Social learning reconsidered

Another thing that is worth mentioning is the social learning process on SNS. Burke, Marlow, and Lento (, 945–54) show that Facebook users tend to, or may be persuaded to, post more photos when they notice that their friends, or just acquaintances, are posting on SNS. The phenomenon, referred to as social learning, is evidence that people are not just autonomous individuals in the Kantian sense, but they perceive and construct themselves by integrating others into their selfness. This is more aligned with a Confucian model of humanity.

Indeed, one paradox of online posting is that people are not aware of the changing boundaries of public and private spheres. Facebook users might not be aware that their posts affect others so much because they still, to a large extent, assume that their influence is limited to the private sphere. Sometimes people even are shocked about their public information being posted online (Noble and Associates ). It would certainly be helpful if SNS would consider this concern, and make people more aware about what can be done with their posts.

What the tian xia view demands is not just that awareness of one's posts be raised, namely to make people think twice before posting anything. Tian xia fundamentally affirms the normative status of social learning in the first place; that is to say, one's activities online, both personal and public, have a tian xia dimension which should aim to be a moral exemplar for bai xin around the world.

If this is the case, the tian xia view would require SNS to give more specific suggestions to users, to make them more attentive to the positive and negative implications of their posts in online communities. A father who is about to post about a joyful time with his son might be notified right before he clicks the “share” button that there are a hundred fathers on his friends list. Perhaps this sounds a bit too demanding or too paternalistic. However, many people would agree that public figures, such as politicians and celebrities, should be more aware of their behavior. We become semi‐public figures when we are on SNS, and it is our choice to do so. When our private lives are viewed by hundreds, if not thousands of friends or followers, our families becomes spaces in which we practice our morality as exemplars for others.

Again, the actualization of this idea is both a philosophical and engineering question that requires much refined deliberation beyond which I cannot elaborate here. The thorny problem we are still facing is to balance consideration for individual freedom with considerations around responsibility. This is both a principle‐based and culturally sensitive issue that constantly catches our attention.

Conclusion

In this article, I have discussed compatibility issues regarding Internet use, SNS in particular, and Confucian ethics. I have reviewed arguments made by Bockover () and Wong (), who claim that Internet use is not compatible with Confucian ethics. I argued that both Bockover and Wong's arguments are based on a particular interpretation of Confucianism which fails to capture its comprehensiveness. I then explained the concept of tian xia, which is both a cosmological and moral concept that considers everyone under heaven as family members. I argued that such a concept suggests that using SNS is not only compatible with Confucian ethics, but that Confucian ethics can positively contribute to redesigning SNS.

Note here that SNS certainly evolve quickly, along with culture, and in response to new applications. I am in no position to affirm the absolute authority of one particular culture, and thereby demand change in SNS. Nor do I agree that we should design SNS without being aware of their cultural dimensions. Culture and technology mutually respond and reshape each other, and philosophical study needs to be innovative so as to catch up with them. My discussions here cannot cover all the possible changes that Confucian SNS might demand, as it is not possible to discuss these matters in much detail here due to length considerations. However, if my arguments above are sound, I should have created some avenues along which the future of SNS should be reconsidered.

Acknowledgments

This work was conducted in the philosophy department of Beijing Normal University and funded by Beijing Normal University as an independent project for distinctive young scholars—Grant 00900/310400088. The article was first presented in the “East Meets West” conference held by Utrecht University in the Netherlands. The author would like to thank Professor Heiner Roetz from Bochum University for his comments on the early version of the paper. Particular thanks go to Pak‐hang Wong for his comments on the paper over the course of several quite intense discussions.

Notes

  1. See The 35th Report on the Internet Development in China. Accessed July 19, 2015, .
  2. Note here that Confucianism surely includes diverse meanings and schools of thought. When I refer to Confucianism, I mainly discuss Confucianism as an ethical school with its related idea of the good life. Moreover, I refer to the pre‐Qin school when discussing Bockover's and Wong's work, but I shift to investigate neo‐Confucianism in the Ming dynasty when tian xia is under investigation.
  3. Mencius argues that the king has the obligation to provide education and formulate good policies so that people can have a decent life. “Let mulberry trees be planted around households of five mu, and people of fifty will be able to be clothed in silk. In the raising of chickens, pigs, dogs, and swine, let not their times of breeding be neglected, and persons of seventy years may eat flesh.…Let careful attention be paid to education in schools, including especially the filial and fraternal duties, and grey‐haired men not be seen upon the roads carrying burdens on their backs or on their heads.…” Mu is a measure of area; 6.6 mu equal 1 acre (Legge , Mencius 1A: 3).
  4. Zhu Xi sees family life as an indispensable step toward achieving moral potential in his specific methodology for approaching morality. He proposes an approach called ge wu zhi zhi, meaning that one should study the nature of things in order to be enlightened by moral knowledge. In this way, one is required to learn from family life in order to be moral (Huang , 809–90).
  5. The neo‐Confucianism I quote here refers to the Song (960–1279)—Ming (1368–1644) Confucian thoughts, particularly the pioneer thinkers Zhu Xi and Wang Yangming.
  6. Zhou li is the rites system of the Zhou dynasty (1100–221 bce).
  7. I am fully aware that this interpretation, as a novel reconstruction, is Kantian and can be further extended to cover the cognitive function of liang zhi. Wang Yangming surely did not reason in this way, and I suspect that he said nothing analytically about how liang zhi could judge between right and wrong. Yet my short reconstruction here, being genuine and consistent with the original position of Wang, helps us to understand the idea of the practical necessity of liang zhi more analytically.
  8. Bai xin is the particular term for describing people living on Earth. It is different from the Western concept of citizenship in many ways. Bai xin is not necessarily affiliated with any sovereignty, only necessarily affiliated with family bond and morality. The term literally means “the people with moral conscience in different family names.”

References

Bell, Daniel A.2010. China's New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday Life in a Changing Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Bockover, Mary I.2003. “Confucian Values and the Internet: A Potential Conflict.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy  30: 159–75.

Boyd, D. M.2008. “Why Youth ♥ Social Network Sites: The Role of Networked Publics in Teenage Social Life  .” In Youth, Identity, and Digital Media, edited by DavidBuckingham, 119–42. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Boyd, Danah. 2010. “Social Network Sites as Networked Publics: Affordances, Dynamics, and Implications  .” In Networked Self: Identity, Community, and Culture on Social Network Sites, edited by ZiziPapacharissi, 39–58. New York, NY: Routledge.

Burke, Moira, CameronMarlow, and ThomasLento. 2009. “Feed Me: Motivating Newcomer Contribution in Social Network Sites.” In Proceedings of the 27th International Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems  , 945–54. Boston, MA: ACM Press.

Chen, Fulong, and Chen, Guofu. 2004. “The Contribution of Confucian Ethics in Online Communication.” Lanzhou Academic Journal  1: 153–54.

Chen, Rongjie. 2009. Wang Yangming's Chuanxilu: A Commentary. Shanghai, China: East China Normal University Press.

Chen, Rongjie. 2012. Zhu Xi Study. Beijing, China: San Lian Press.

Du, Zhengteng. 2011. The City‐State of the Zhou Dynasty. Taipei, Taiwan: Lian Jing Press.

Fogg, Brian J.2002. “Persuasive Technology: Using Computers to Change What We Think and Do.” Ubiquity  2002 (December): 5.

He, Xinhua. 2005. “The View of Tian Xia: A Regional Experience to Build a New World Order.” Twenty One Century Journal (in Chinese). Available at http://www.cuhk.edu.hk/ics/21c/supplem/essay/0409072g.htm.

Huang, Zongxi. 1986. The Study of Song and Yuan (song yuan xue an). Beijing, China: Zhong Hua Shu Ju Press.

IJsselsteijn, Wijnand, YvonnedeKort, CeesMidden, BerryEggen, and ElisevandenHoven. 2006. In Proceedings Persuasive Technology: First International Conference on Persuasive Technology for Human Well‐Being, PERSUASIVE 2006, Eindhoven, The Netherlands, May 18–19, 2006. Berlin, Germany: Springer.

Jaeger, Paul T.2005. “Deliberative Democracy and the Conceptual Foundations of Electronic Government.” Government Information Quarterly  22: 702–19.

Korsgaard, Christine M.2008. The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Legge, James. 1991a. The Chinese Classics with a Translation, Critical and Exegetical Notes, Prolegomena, and Copious Indexes: Confucian Analects, the Great Learning, and the Doctrine of the Mean. Taipei, Taiwan: SMC Publishing.

Legge, James. 1991b. The Works of Mencius. Taipei, Taiwan: SMC Publishing.

Min, Dahong. 2011. “The Internet Diplomacy of US Government.” The Frontier of Social Science  7: 136–43.

Ni, Peimin. 2014. “Seek and You Will Find It; Let Go and You Will Lose It: Exploring a Confucian Approach to Human Dignity.” Dao  13: 173–98.

Noble, Phil, and Associates. 2001. “E‐Democracy around the World.” Survey for the Bertelsmann Foundation  , Summer. Available at http://web.umoncton.ca/umcm‐sitesgr/cybergouvernement/noble.pdf.

Tan, Youzhi. 2010. “Internet Diplomacy: A New Weapon of US Government.” International Forum  1: 74–78.

van denHoven, J., and K.Jacob. 2013. Options for Strengthening Responsible Research and Innovation: Report of the Expert Group on the State of Art in European Responsible Research and Innovation. Luxembourg, Luxembourg: Publications Office of the European Union.

VanSchomberg, René. 2011. Toward Responsible Research and Innovation in the Information and Communication Technologies and Security Technologies Fields. Luxembourg, Luxembourg: Publications Office of the European Union.

Wang, Mingming. 2012. “All Under Heaven (Tian Xia): Cosmological Perspectives and Political Ontologies in Pre‐Modern China.” HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory  2: 337–83.

Wong, Pak‐hang. 2012. “Dao, Harmony and Personhood: Towards a Confucian Ethics of Technology.” Philosophy and Technology  25: 67–86.

Wong, Pak‐hang. 2013. “Confucian Social Media: An Oxymoron?” Dao  12: 283–96.

Xun, Kuang. 2007. Xun zi. Beijing, China: Zhong Hua Shu Ju Press.

Yangming, Wang. 2006. The Complete Works of Wang Yangming. Shanghai, China: Shanghai Classics Publishing House.

Yu, Bingyi, and Zhao, Iulu. 2000. “Confucianism and Modernity: Insights from an Interview with Tu Wei‐ming.” China Review International  7: 377–87.

Yuan, Peiqiu, and ZengChangqiu. 2004. “Confucian Ethics: Towards a Rational Restoration of Cyber Morality.” Guangdong Social Science  4: 67–72.

Zhao, Tingyang. 2006. “Rethinking Empire from a Chinese Concept of Tian Xia.” Social Identities  12: 29–41.

Zhou, Yali. 2008. “Cyber Communication and Demise of of Confucian Tradition.” Youth Journalist  3: 63–64.